[FRA:] Young Horkheimer
Ralph Dumain
rdumain at autodidactproject.org
Wed Mar 25 21:39:58 GMT 2009
<http://www.ethicalpolitics.org/seminars/horkheimer-young.htm>Young
Horkheimer: Critical Theory Before the Dialectic
of Enlightenment, And After It by Matthew Sharpe (2007)
Sharpe claims the Young Horkheimer has been
eclipsed (eclipse of reason?), partly on account
of the pervasive influence of Dialectic of
Enlightenment, which can be seen as a reneging on
his original interdisciplinary program. Sharpe
is interested in Horkheimer's work preceding his
key essay on critical vs traditional theory, in
which the terminology of critical theory
supplants that of Marxism. Young Horkheimer of
the early 1930s calls himself a materialist,
translating metaphysics back into history, and it
is his materialism that Sharpe wants to reclaim.
"As Robert Stirk has commented, Horkheimers
early essays on the history of bourgeois society
undoubtedly contain the key to his political
philosophy. Having completed his doctorate and
Habilitationschrift under the neoKantian Hans
Cornelius, from 1925-1930 Horkheimer lectured at
Frankfurt on the history of philosophy. In this
time, he conducted a series of detailed studies
on bourgeois thinkers, from Machiavelli and the
theologians of the reformation to Kant, which
formed the basis of the 1930 Anfange der
Burgerlichen Geschichsohilosophie. Yet, even in
the paradigmatic 1995 collection On Max
Horkheimer, comparatively little attention has
been paid to Horkheimers early history of the
modern period and its ideas. This is all the more
remarkable, given the fame Horkheimers later,
speculative philosophy of history, contained in
the Dialectic of Enlightenment, and the very
contrast these earlier essays exhibit when read
alongside this text. In them, fascism is
conceived not as the completion of a process
beginning with the Homeric Greeks, but as the
symptom of the self-contradictions intrinsic to
European modernity, beginning in the Italian renaissance."
Skipping down a bit:
"The result is that these essays not only contain
many of Horkheimers arguably most valuable, and
certainly most nuanced, contributions to the
history of ideas. They also present themselves
and this is my interest today as perhaps the
place to look if we are to seek out in the
Horkheimer of before the dialectic of
enlightenment theoretical concepts which might
still have something new to say to us in todays particular conjuncture."
Sharpe then addresses Horkheimers The Latest
Attack on Metaphysics (1934), directed against
logical positivism. Horkheimer saw the scientific
revolution as progressive, but he also placed in
the context of the aggressive bid of the emerging
bourgeoisie for power, freeing up the masses from
feudal servitude and making them freely
exploitable by capital. The harnessing and
subjugation of the rebellious tendencies of the
popular masses led to an early "aestheticization
of politics" on the part of the bourgeoisie and a
preoccupation with demagoguery and the mob.
"In the cultural sphere, young Horkheimer argues
that the chaotic lack of coordination between
the sciences which motivates his
interdisciplinary program in social research
itself reflects the contradictory anatomy of
the market-regulated civil society of the modern
period. On the one hand, the positive sciences
presuppositionless lack of reflexivity about
their own social preconditions, he argues, does
make them vulnerable to the uncritical
reproduction of systemically promoted principles
of utilisation, exploitation, and
administration (Bon) although, as we have
seen, there is no sense in the early essays that
the sciences, or rationality per se, could be
reduced to these instrumental functions. (cf.
Bon) On the other hand, young Horkheimer holds
that the neglect of the dynamic relationships
between the separate object-domains (NSC) of the
different sciences reflects, within the cultural
sphere, the more general antinomies of bourgeois
society. The contradiction between the
quantitative expansion of knowledge within, and
qualitative non-coordination between, different
disciplines, his bold contention is,
symptomatically reproduces the wider
contradiction between general irrationalism
that stands over the micro-economic rationalism
in details of particular capitalist ventures. (SFP)"
Note Horkheimer's concern that . . .
" . . . when modern philosophy attempts to
address the substantive questions of meaning and
morality not addressed by the natural sciences,
it is necessarily distorted by the increasing
inability of subjects to cognitively map the
social process as a whole, . . . . For young
Horkheimer, the re-emergence of scepticism in the
modern age, first in Montaigne (MFS) and later in
Humes deconstructions of personal identity as
fictional or consciousness as a theatre (MFS,
Stirk), already reflect the material
disempowerment underlying the bourgeois paeans
to the autonomous masters and possessors of nature. "
Kant's dichotomies are a manifestation of the divided early modern self.
Horkheimer purports to correct Weber:
[I]rrationalism is from the start no less
associated with [bourgeois] history.
Horkheimer points out the irrationalist
antecedents of the descent into fascism:
"Like Heidegger if only in this much, that is, it
is as an inversion of traditional theory
(McCarthy), rather than its overcoming, that
Horkheimer situates the vitalisms of Nietzsche or
of Bergson whose expression sub specie
durationis indeed indicates the viewpoint of
change, but at the same time infinite change
(Stork) the philosophy of values of Scheler
or Hartmann, and even the death drive of the
later Freud which, like the Devil in the Middle
Ages ... is to be blamed for all evil without
need for any more concrete forms of
social-historical analysis. There is truth in
these species of irrationalism, young Horkheimer
characteristically accedes. Their truth lies in
the insight into the real crisis of
contemporary forms of positivistic rationalism.
Their falsity, however and the very clear and
present danger embodied in the thought of Klage,
Schmitt, Junger and Spengler, is to turn this
insight into the vindication for a constellation
of ideas whose defining poles are the
valorisation of a sacrificio intellectus before
the simultaneously immediate and vague Truths
of life, race, the volk or the nation, and in
fascism the channelling of the huge amount
of aggression which are emerging in a climate of
destitution into self-sacrificial devotion
against each particular individual or into a
spirit of battle against national enemies."
What he said!
Sharpe sees this bourgeois dichotomy playing out
in contemporary philosophical ideologies--in the
tug of war between analytical and continental
philosophy. Foucault, Deleuze, Badiou, and
Agamben are singled out, as are the shits who
publish Telos today. Horkheimer matters now because . . .
What Horkheimers earlier position allows us, in
this context, is part of a framework to challenge
what seems to me to be the most vital political
illusion fostered by Hayek et al: the equation
between economic liberty (the freedom to trade)
and civil, social and political liberties. Less
sanguine than the neoliberals, or we have to add,
many post-structuralists about the necessarily
beneficent effects of opening subjects to the
radical uncertainty of a future whose shape they
can be less and less sure of, his position allows
us to come to terms with todays growing
neoconservative reactions across the first world,
which superimpose neotraditionalist cultural
paradigms, combined with post-liberal state
forms, on top of an economic system which is
celebrated as melting everything solid into air.
Sharpe refutes McCarthy's Habermasian position,
as well as Honneth's. As for Horkheimer's alleged "economism":
". . . it was not his earlier economism that
led him down the path to the impasses of The
Dialectic of Enlightenment from 1938 to 1942.
What Postone and Brick document is how
Horkheimers trajectory in the late 1930s was in
fact determined by his uncritical appropriation
of Pollocks argument for the new primacy of the
political in contemporary social reproduction.
Famously, alongside Meyer and Manddelbaum,
Pollock adduced the category of state
capitalism in order to explain politico-economic
developments in Soviet Russia, National Socialist
Germany, and the capitalist countries after the
Great Depression. In each of these regimes,
Pollock maintained, the price and market
mechanisms had been superseded as the means of
distributing the social surplus by systems of
centralised administration. Now: as Postone and
Brick point out, given young Horkheimers hopes
for a more rational organisation of society which
would supersede the chaotic irrationality of
later capitalism, his acceptance of Pollocks
thought had to have a devastating effect."
More information about the theory-frankfurt-school
mailing list