[FRA:] Horkheimer;s moral philosophy
Ralph Dumain
rdumain at autodidactproject.org
Mon Dec 27 06:25:07 GMT 2010
J. C. Berendzen <http://philpapers.org/s/J.%20C.%20Berendzen> (2010).
Suffering and Theory: Max Horkheimer's Early Essays and Contemporary
Moral Philosophy.
<http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/36/9/1019?rss=1>/Philosophy
and Social Criticism/ 36 (9):1019-1037.
I thought I had written about this, but apparently I got distracted by
more urgent tasks immediately after reading it a couple months ago.
Here's the abstract for starters:
*Abstract*
Max Horkheimer does not generally receive the scholarly attention
given to other 'Frankfurt School' figures. This is in part because
his early work seems contradictory, or unphilosophical. For example,
Horkheimer seems, at various points (to use contemporary metaethical
terms), like a constructivist, a moral realist, or a moral skeptic,
and it is not clear how these views cohere. The goal of this article
is to show that the contradictions regarding moral theory exist
largely on the surface, and that one can go below the surface to
reconstruct a coherent position. Part I will examine Horkheimer's
skeptical critique of morality, and show that it leads to the
realist position discussed in part II. Part III then shows that such
realism can only be understood within a larger constructivist
project, which elaborates on a minimal normativity present in human
experience. This reconstruction should make sense of Horkheimer's
work, and show its contemporary relevance.
Actually, I like Horkheimer's work from the 1930s, but I think he blew
his wad during that decade, and there's not much left after that. But I
was always interested in his treatment of epistemology and metaphysics,
never thought about moral theory, a subject that doesn't interest me
anyway. Berendzen traces three phases or variations of the moral theory
he find in Horkheimer, which B labels constructivist, realist, and
skeptical positions.
I: Horkheimer's moral skepticism
In 'Materialism and Morality' H can be seen as a skeptic. This
involves, inter alia, an attack on Kant's untenable position. The
critique of morality is bound up with the critique of idealism.
II: moral realism
Examples: /Dammerung/, 'Materialism and Metaphysics', viz. the emphasis
on suffering, influence of Schopenhauer. Horkheimer:
[The] materialist view has the negative significance that it rejects
a metaphysically grounded morality. But in addition it has always
meant to materialists that man's striving for happiness is to be
recognized as a natural fact requiring no justification.
This, according to B, is a naturalistic, hence realist position. But is
the desire for alleviation of suffering merely subjective and emotive? B
argues no, citing the criterion of objective knowledge of social
interests advocated in 'Traditional and Critical Theory', and also
insisting on the collective nature of the struggle for well-being.
Horkheimer is in fact pro-science, but not so in relation to the
fragmented, detached role of the specialist. For this latter reason,
Horkheimer is carried beyong realism, and this leads to his
constructivist dimension.
III: Horkheimer's constructivism
H's 1935 essay 'On the Problem of Truth' is aggressively realist. Does
this contradict his skepticism? B sees a link with constructivism. H
modifies the correspondence theory of truth:
This correspondence is neither a simple datum [nor] an immediate
fact. . . . Rather, it is always established by real events and
human activity. Already in the investigation and determination of
facts, and even more in the verification of theories, a role is
played by the direction of attention, the refinement of methods, the
categorical structure of the subject matter -- in short, by human
activity corresponding to the given social period.
B elaborates this position, but I lack the patience to do so.
Comparisons are made with Rawls and others.
One can see the fusion of realist and constructivist elements, e.g.:
But if [critical theory's] concepts, which sprang from social
movements, today seem empty because no one stands behind them but
its pursuing persecutors, yet the truth of them will out. For the
thrust toward a rational society, which admittedly seems to exist
today only in the realms of fantasy, is really innate in every man.
. . . That is not a claim that should bring a sigh of relief. For
the realization of possibilities depends on historical conflicts.
The truth about the future does not take the form of a verification
of data.
That's H. B says:
Horkheimer's views are not, upon reflection, incoherent. He is a
moral skeptic only insofar as he is skeptical of the idea that there
are universal moral rules that moral philosophy can discern and then
apply irrespective of particular circumstances. Such views are
problematic not only for epistemological reasons (that they overlook
the historical character of knowledge) but for broadly moral
reasons. Their lack of attention to the problems faced by real,
particular human beings leads to real suffering. The experience of
suffering, and the desire for happiness, are empirical realities
that motivate us to seek social change. But this motivation issues
not universal oughts but only a weak normative force that must be
fleshed out through the construction of a philosophically guided
research program that can determine real strategies for working
toward overcoming suffering.
B finds H's position appealing. I take no position on B's
interpretation; here I am just a reporter, however spotty my reportage.
More information about the theory-frankfurt-school
mailing list