[FRA:] Adorno vs. authenticity
Ralph Dumain
rdumain at igc.org
Sun Jan 28 16:55:52 GMT 2007
Jay, Martin. Taking On the Stigma of Inauthenticity: Adornos Critique of
Genuineness, New German Critique, no. 97, Winter 2006, pp. 15-30.
Jay commences with a quote from Marshall Bermans The Politics of
Authenticity (1970). While authenticity was held up as a virtue by
intellectuals of the 20th century, especially in the United States, this
alleged virtue has German roots, subjected to severe scrutiny by Theodor
Adorno, inter alia in his critique of Heidegger, The Jargon of
Authenticity. Adorno saw authenticity as an essentially conservative and
conformist force and specifically German. Later I shall return to Jays
odd leap from America to Germany, and from 60s radicalism to German
fascism, but first, we must follow Jays presentation of the German situation.
Jays analysis begins with Walter Benjamins The Work of Art in the Age of
Mechanical Reproduction. In the medieval period, authenticity would have
been a meaningless concept. As Jay quotes Eve Geulen on Benjamins position:
In the beginning was not the original, but the reproduction, which makes
the concept of authenticity possible in the first place. Authenticity
becomes authentic only against the background of reproducibility. That
means, however, that authenticity is compromised from the beginning,
inauthentic from the start, for its origin lies not in itself, but rather
in its opposite, reproduction. (19)
Adorno expands on this position in aphorism 99, Gold Assay, of Minima
Moralia. He sees genuineness as filling the vacuum of traditional
religious and ethical standards. But while authenticity was the watchword
of 19th century bourgeois intellectuals like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and
Ibsen, in the 20th century it has found a home in fascism. (20) Adorno also
draws on Benjamins view of mimesis and denies the existence of a pure
subject prior to mimetic behavior. (21) Adorno also has some harsh words
for Kierkegaard and Nietzsche. As Jay puts it:
Because the self is always imbricated in the social, any attempt, like
Kierkegaards, to retreat into naked existential interiority is
complicitous with the isolation caused by society, not a protest against
it. Nietzsche, despite all his insights into the workings of ideology,
failed to see through the fallacy of authenticity, which betrayed his
Lutheran roots and smacked of the very anti-Semitism he decried in Wagner.
(21-22)
Adorno traces the contemporaneous jargon of authenticity to religious
revivalists, dubbed sarcastically as The Authentic Ones, who pushed
Kierkegaard in the 1920s. While the jargon, which Adorno characterizes as
the unending mumble of the liturgy of inwardness, speaks of higher things
but lacks the substance, it reeks of what Benjamin wrote about the aura.
To sum up, then, Adorno's multifarious charges against authenticity and the
jargon around it are as follows: it provides a hollow substitute for lost
religious belief in ultimate values; it is based on a mistaken search for
proprietary origins that establish rights of the earliest settlers; it
rests on a dubious ideal of self-possession and integrity, which fails to
credit the mimetic moment in the creation of selfhood; it entails an
ontological fiction of absoluteness that falsely sees itself as the
antidote to the leveling equivalence of the exchange principle; it serves
as an anti-intellectual evocation of concreteness and immediacy against the
alleged depredations of abstract, intellectual thought; it can be
understood as a variant of the cultish notion of aura, which itself is only
a function of the reproductive technologies that it pretends to antedate;
and, finally, it paradoxically gives too much power to the subject able to
designate something as authentic and to the object after that designation
has been made. All attempts to derive authentic meaning from etymological
priority thus share with foundational philosophy a vain search for an
Urgeschichte, which is little more than a nostalgic fantasy of primal
wholeness before the Fall. (25)
It is unfortunate that Jay doesnt connect this back to the USA at this
point, for I have two immediate associations. But first, on Marshall
Berman: Berman is a 60s radical who more recently wrote books on modernity
and Marxism. This should be kept in mind, as the heritage of existentialism
in the USA is, in my view, dual. The key reference here is:
Cotkin, George. Existential America. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press, 2003.
Cotkin doesnt draw the distinction I do, but it is plain that
existentialism has served both reactionary and revolutionary aims in the
USA. The Kierkegaard boom was essentially conservative (with notable
exceptions such as its influence on Richard Wright), a doctrine of
self-satisfied resignation to the status quo: you know the routine: man is
sinful, and we cant change society for the better. Cotkin repeatedly uses
the word chastened to describe the mood of a significant sector of the
intelligentsia. This helps to explain, inadvertently, why C.L.R. James so
hated American intellectuals--and existentialism--in the 1940s.
On the other hand, existentialism exerted quite a different influence on
black intellectuals, from Richard Wright to Ralph Ellison to several
activists of the civil rights movement to the New Left. In this case, one
should review which authors were favored. My recollection is dim, but I
believe that, for the 60s generation, Camus and Sartre served as models; I
dont recall anything about Kierkegaard or Heidegger.
But now it occurs to me that the critique of authenticity in Germany might
bear some application to the Beat poets of the USA, at least to some of
them, Kerouac in particular. Ginsberg was a sweet-natured fellow who was
not very discriminating in the company he kept. Kerouac, Cassady,
Burroughs, not to mention the Hells Angels--riffraff! (But then, there are
other Beat poets to be considered, not least, the leading black Beat
poets--Ted Joans and Bob Kaufman--who, as is typical for this country, tend
to be forgotten when the Beats are celebrated. LeRoi Jones /Amiri Baraka
is less likely to be ignored, but then he is one of these questionable
characters; cf., e.g. the book by Jerry Gafio Watts.) But as a cultural
phenomenon with Kerouac as the titular guru, there is something here to be
questioned about authenticity and religiosity with dubious content. An
even better example of this phenomenon would be that consummate asshole Ken
Kesey, subject of another hollow poseur, Tom Wolfe, in The Electric
Kool-Aid Acid Test.
OK, back to Jay. He says that, in spite of all this, Adorno still maintains
an alternative conception of authenticity, using the word Authentizität
rather than Eigenlichkeit. (26) He has been criticized for this, wrongly
by Douglas Kellner according to Jay. (27)
Jay sums up:
The ideological notion of authenticity, attacked in aphorism 99 and The
Jargon of Authenticity, is based on a dangerous search for ultimate origins
as legitimating fictions, a mistaken reification of the individual as a
self-possessed monad and of the transfer of cultish notions of aura from
religion to art, philosophy, and everyday human existence. It evokes the
myth of autochthonous rootedness to denigrate the wanderers condemned to
permanent exile.
Against this usage are two more defensible notions, which are variants of
nonauratic authenticity. One involves the registering of modern life's
historical disasters, the "scars of damage and disruption" that produce a
shudder emblematic of the work's truth-content. Here authenticity means
fidelity to the historical moment, with all its traumatic contradictions,
rather than retreat to an allegedly prior state of plenitudinous wholeness
before the fall into alienation. However vigorously he may have insisted on
the value of aesthetic autonomy against the reduction of art to a function
of something exterior to it, Adorno never failed to praise works that
indirectly expressed the depredations of modern life. Indeed, only the
works that resist the gravitational pull of the current order and yet do
not pretend to have transcended it entirely--works that, as Max Paddison
has pointed out, are "failures" and know themselves as such--can gain the
breathing space to express its horrors."
The second defensible use harks back to Benjamin's celebration of the
mimetic faculty, which is evident in the technologically reproduced mass
culture that Adorno so often distrusted. In this context, authenticity
paradoxically means accepting and even valorizing the necessary
inauthenticity of the self, which is always dependent on the other, always
in relation to the outside, always insufficiently integrated into a
coherent and boundaried unit. (29)
Jay concludes: Adorno appropriated the ideas of others, and he also laid
himself open regarding his own position in the scheme of things, not to
claim authenticity for himself. (30)
More information about the theory-frankfurt-school
mailing list