[FRA:] Dubiel, Helmut. Theory and Politics (1)

steve.devos at krokodile.co.uk steve.devos at krokodile.co.uk
Tue Feb 28 19:46:09 GMT 2006


So have you changed your opinion of the book in the last two decades ? 
Especially given the question at the end...

Doug Kellner wrote:

> Here's my review from mid-80s when the Dubiel book first came out=
> b:dubiel.rev
>
>
>
> Helmut Dubiel, Theory and Politics.  Studies in the Development of 
> Critical Theory, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. and London, England, 
> 1985), xiii and 207 pages; translated by Benjamin Gregg.
>
>
>
> Benjamin Gregg's translation of Helmut Dubiel's 1978 book 
> Wissenschaftsorganisation und politische Erfahrung: Studien zur fruhen 
> Kritischen Theorie) makes  accessible  to English-speaking readers one 
> of the most important books yet to appear on the theory and politics 
> of the so-called Frankfurt school. Dubiel provides the best available 
> historical and analytical account of the development of critical 
> theory, of its method of interdisciplinary social research, and of how 
> it organized and pursued its research projects during its years under 
> Horkheimer's directorship in Weimar Germany and in exile in the United 
> States during the era of fascism. In the first half of his book, 
> Dubiel focuses on "political experience and the process of theory 
> construction in the Frankfurt circle, 1930-1945."  His study shows 
> that, at least during this period, the Institute for Social Research 
> was extremely interested in history, politics, and the relation of its 
> work to its historical situation and revolutionary politics.  The 
> texts, correspondence, and other material cited provides a strong 
> defense against criticisms that critical theory is primarily 
> apolitical, uninterested in history and politics, idealistic, and 
> hostile to science. Dubiel's research makes it clear that the critical 
> theorists took different positions during varying historical periods 
> toward their socio-historical situation, politics, science, and theory.
>
>    Dubiel divides the work of the Institute for Social Research during 
> the period under scrutiny into three distinct stages: 1) materialism, 
> 1930-1937; 2) critical theory, 1937-1940; 3) the critique of 
> instrumental reason, 1940-1945.  He differentiates these stages 
> according to the general theoretical position maintained,  the 
> political position and presentation of the theory-practice relation, 
> and their specific historical experience and positions toward the 
> working class movement, fascism, and the Soviet Union during the 
> period under question. Dubiel thus contributes both to a better 
> understanding of the genesis of critical theory and to its 
> developments under specific politico-historical  and theoretical 
> exigencies. In characterizing the theory-praxis relation he 
> distinguishes between the varying subjects and addressees of the 
> theory and their differing conceptions of the relation between theory 
> and practice in various historical contexts.  In particular, he shows 
> how critical theory began by addressing itself to a revolutionary 
> proletariat as part of the revolutionary movement and ended by 
> addressing primarily other radical intellectuals in political isolation.
>
>    In characterizing the dominant theoretical position during each 
> stage, Dubiel analyzes the specific "self-understanding within the 
> tradition of historical and political theory," the relation to 
> Marxism, the relation of philosophy to science, and the concept of 
> utopia operative. This sort of careful, differentiated historical and 
> theoretical analysis makes possible appreciation of the heterogeneity 
> of critical theory during its "heroic," or "classical," period and the 
> significant developments within critical theory that have been 
> generally overlooked by most historians or followers of critical 
> theory, especially within the English-speaking world.  Theory and 
> Politics thus provides an indispensible source for understanding both 
> the history of critical theory and its fundamental theoretical 
> position(s).
>
>
>
> Dubiel argues that the, first, "materialism" phase of critical theory 
> is distinguished by commitment to a materialist social theory defined 
> by the unity of philosophy and science (11-38) and rooted in the 
> marxian critique of political economy.  The distinctive contribution 
> of this stage was development of a marxian social psychology and the 
> major research project was a study of the social-psychological 
> structure of employees in the Weimar Republic--which was recently 
> published for the first time as @U(Arbeiter und Angestellte am 
> Vorabend des Dritten Reiches) (Stuttgart: Deutsche-Verlags Anstalt, 
> 1980) and was translated as The Working Class in Weimar Germany 
> (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1984)). Politically, 
> there was "critical solidarity with the 'revolutionary wing of the 
> working-class movement'" which characterized  the political 
> orientation of the group (17).
>
>
>
>     Eschewing both the mechanistic metaphysical materialism already 
> criticized by Marx in The Holy Family, as well as the current 
> positivistic forms of materialism, Horkheimer and his colleagues 
> defined the objects of materialist theory in terms of existing social 
> struggles, problems, and experiences. Rejecting Hegel's identity 
> theory (and thus the forms of epistemological realism held to by many 
> positivistic materialists then and now), for the critical theorists 
> there was a non-identity between concept and object; their concepts 
> and theories thus provided but pictures of the socio-material world 
> and not any absolute or indubitable knowledge.  As Horkheimer wrote, 
> "'Materialist theory...is not a metaphysics of history but a picture 
> of the world that changes and develops in the context of practical 
> efforts to improve it'" (33).
>
>
>
> The materialist theory of society developed by Horkheimer and his 
> colleagues was closely related to Marxism at this stage: "'Materialism 
> is characterized by its content: the economic theory of society'" 
> (34).  During this stage, the Institute saw its purpose as 
> reformulating Marxian theory "under the historically changed 
> conditions of capitalism and the labor movement" (34). This involved 
> moving beyond crude marxian conceptions of the relation between base 
> and superstructure and developing both a marxist social psychology and 
> cultural theory to better analyze the mediations between the economic 
> base and the realms of the superstructure.
>
>
>
> The Institute's social theory during this phase was a response both to 
> inadequacies within classical Marxism and the dominant forms of 
> bourgeois science.  Orthodox Marxism had congealed into a dogmatic, 
> reductionist, objectivistic metaphysical materialism, and bourgeois 
> social science was characterized by a fragmentation of the sciences, 
> each cut off from the other and pursuing its investigations isolated 
> from other disciplines.  To overcome this dual crisis of Marxism and 
> bourgeois science, the Institute attempted to develop an 
> "interdisciplinary materialism" that would be characterized by an 
> integration of philosophy and science. Accordingly, during the 1930s 
> the Institute developed criticisms of both the abstract, speculative 
> and metaphysical philosophy dominant in Germany at the time and the 
> various specialized sciences. Thus, the project of constructing an 
> interdisciplinary "materialist superscience" was conceived in 
> opposition to both the specialized bourgeois sciences and the 
> socialist scientism of many orthodox social democrats like Kautsky or 
> communists like Stalin. As Horkheimer stated at the time:
>
>
>
> "'Materialism requires the unification of philosophy and science. Of 
> course, it recognizes technical differences between the more general 
> research of philosophy and the more specialized research in the 
> sciences, just as it recognizes differences in method between research 
> and presentation but not between science and philosophy as such'" (36).
>
>
>
> And in his inaugural address after taking over as Director of
>
> the Institute, Horkheimer argued:
>
>
>
> "'What matters today... is to organize investigations on the basis of 
> current philosophical problems that unite philosophers, sociologists, 
> economists, historians, and psychologists in an ongoing research 
> community that can do together what in other disciplines one 
> individual alone does in the laboratory, what genuine scientists have 
> always done: pursue those questions aimed at the view of the whole, 
> using the most refined scientific methods; reformulate the questions 
> in the course of work as demanded by the object; make more precise and 
> develop new methods without losing sight of general considerations'" 
> (36).
>
>
>
> During its "interdisciplinary materialism" stage, the Institute 
> members saw themselves as part of the revolutionary labor movement, 
> and supported efforts for a planned economy and the construction of 
> socialism in the Soviet Union; they also saw fascism, in rather 
> orthodox marxian terms, as the product of capitalism in crisis.  
> Dubiel's study is especially valuable for the way that it assembles 
> materials defining both the Institute's theoretical and political 
> positions at different stages of development, and how its members 
> conceived the relation between theory and politics at different 
> junctues.  Dubiel's assembled quotations are extremely well-chosen and 
> illuminating and provide a useful compendium of Institute positions on 
> both theory and politics.  In particular, he shows that, contrary to 
> some misimpressions, the Institute took rather systematic and 
> well-defined positions toward the political issues and movements of 
> the day--at least until the 1940s.
>
>
>
> During what Dubiel sees as the Insitute's second stage, they 
> explicitly adopted the term  "critical theory" to characterize their 
> work.  This stage (1937-1940) is marked by the defeat of the labor 
> movement in Germany, the triumph of fascism, and increasing doubts 
> about the Soviet Union as revelations of its trials, labor camps, and 
> stalinist deformations became wide-spread.  This historical situation  
> required new reflections on the relation between politics and theory, 
> the role of the radical intellectual, and the nature of socialism.  In 
> essays published during this stage both Horkheimer and Marcuse 
> "expressly emphasize that a change in property relations implies 
> merely a negative precondition for the building of a socialist 
> society" (42).  As Marcuse put it: "'Without freedom and happiness in 
> the social relations of human beings, even the greatest increase in 
> production, even the abolition of private property in the means of 
> production, remains infected with the old injustices'" (42).
>
>
>
> At this time, the Institute  adopted the term "critical theory" to 
> define their theoretical position in part because conditions of exile 
> in the United States forced them to adopt code words to describe their 
> project to cover over their commitments to Marxism in an environment 
> that was quite hostile to Marxism.   The label stuck and  many of its 
> inner circle utilized it to define themselves to the present, and the 
> Institute's theoretical labors as a whole are frequently subsumed 
> under the blanket concept of "critical theory," though as Dubiel 
> shows, this term was first coined in 1937 and henceforth was used to 
> cover work in different contexts that was often quite different.
>
>
>
> Theory and Politics documents the conditions and texts whereby the 
> Institute developed a radical, neo-Marxian  social theory more 
> appropriate to a situation when radical intellectuals are segregated, 
> isolated, and marginalized.  Dubiel derives the title of the first 
> section of  his study from  this situation: "the integration of the 
> proletariat and the loneliness of the intelligentsia."  Critical 
> theory represents a stage in the development of neo-marxist social 
> theories during which radical intellectuals were separated from 
> revolutionary socialist movements and fascism steadily gained power 
> throughout the world. The Institute theorists were among the first to 
> characterize this situation and to make explicit the problems for the 
> marxian theory of revolution when the working class was defeated or 
> integrated into capitalist societies.  This, of course, remains one of 
> the defining features of the trajectory of critical theory to this day 
> and points to why the Institute felt it was necessary to update and 
> revise both the marxian theory and critique of capitalism, as well as 
> the marxian theory of revolution and the transition from capitalism to 
> socialism.
>
>
>
> Thus, as Dubiel puts it, "By 1937, the subject and addressee of 
> revolutionary theory are separated much more clearly in the Frankfurt 
> Circle's political self-interpretation.  Horkheimer maintains 
> repeatedly that, for the sake of the adequacy of the theory, the 
> critical intellectual must be able to endure marginalization from the 
> addressee of his theoretical work" (53). During this period, 
> Horkheimer and his colleagues radicalized and developed their 
> critiques of what they called "traditional theory" and further 
> developed their theoretical position.  The political impasse evidently 
> inspired more sustained theoretical labors.  The critical theorists 
> still advocated a synthesis of philosophy and the sciences (63) but 
> seemed more open to various empirical sciences and more critical of 
> classical marxism. During the 1930s and early 40s, the critical 
> theorists continued their work in developing interdisciplinary social 
> theory and intensified efforts to develop a theory of 
> fascism--projects that I shall shortly return to as they are the 
> subject of the second half of Dubiel's book.
>
>
>
> But probably the most significant development in the trajectory of the 
> Institute's development was abandonment of the project of 
> interdisciplinary social theory for production of the critique of 
> instrumental reason which found classical expression in Adorno's and 
> Horkheimer's @U(Dialectic of Enlightenment) (1947).  Although Dubiel 
> describes the continued demise of the labor movement, spread of 
> fascism, and oppressive developments in the Soviet Union at this time, 
> he does not adequately explicate the conditions which led to the 
> rather dramatic departures from their earlier theoretical 
> enterprises.  While Dubiel notes the impact of WW II  (76) on the 
> development of critical theory, he does not analyze in any detail the 
> breaking up of the Institute's interdisciplinary group; this happened 
> in part  because Horkheimer was forced to go to California on account 
> of his health and because many of the Institute inner circle and other 
> colleagues joined the U.S. government as part of their struggle 
> against fascism.  At this time, Adorno and Horkheimer took over the 
> development of critical theory and this stage is particularly marked 
> by the imprint of Adorno's particular ideas and style of writing--a 
> point not adequately explicated by Dubiel who tends to present 
> Horkheimer as the demiurge of critical theory.
>
>
>
> Adorno's and Horkheimer's work during this period is addressed to 
> "critical intellectuals" and the pretense that they were writing for a 
> temporarily defeated revolutionary movement is surrendered. Likewise, 
> the attempt to integrate philosophy and the social sciences is 
> replaced by more aggressive philosophical theorizing and speculation.  
> Given that both Adorno and Horkheimer were trained as philosophers, 
> and in the absence of the interdisciplinary research Institute, it is 
> not surprising that critical theory would turn more philosophical and 
> radicalize its critique of science. This development was also 
> conditioned by the instrumentalization of science and technology in 
> the Nazi and other war machines and by Adorno's and Horkheimer's 
> growing aversion to the sort of scientific philosophy and positivistic 
> science dominant in the United States.  Consequently, the critique of 
> instrumental reason and the "dialectic of enlightenment" replaced the 
> earlier marxian emphasis on class struggle and materialist social 
> analysis with a focus on the primacy of the relation between humans 
> and nature, in which marxism, enlightenment rationality, science and 
> technology, the culture industries, and the trends of development of 
> both capitalist and socialist societies were interpreted under the 
> rubric of the "dialectic of enlightenment." In this theory, projects 
> like Marxism and science, intended to contribute to the domination of 
> nature, turned into more powerful instruments for the domination of 
> human beings.
>
>
>
> On a theoretical and political level, Dubiel provides a fine analysis 
> of the changed political and theoretical position developed by Adorno 
> and Horkheimer during this period (67-97). Again, he chooses key 
> passages to express their political isolation, their pessimistic 
> conclusion that henceforth political radicalism could only survive in 
> select critical intellectuals, and their more apocalyptic and elusive 
> style of writing. Dubiel makes clear, against some of the devotees of 
> critical theory, that important discontinuities emerged within the 
> trajectory of critical theory and that the most significant 
> discontinuities emerged in the 1940s in the break between this stage 
> and the two earlier stages of development.
>
>
>
> I would, however, take issue with some of Dubiel's conclusions stated 
> in summary form after his historical, political, and theoretical 
> analysis of the key stages of development within the Institute.  He 
> claims that "The labor movement's demise at the end of the Weimar 
> Republic was the most significant experience undergone by the Circle" 
> (99).  This judgement is somewhat misleading, and I would argue 
> instead that the experiences of fascism and emigration were the 
> crucial determinants of key features of critical theory.  The inner 
> circle of the Institute was never particularly interested in the 
> vicissitudes of the labor movement and, in any case, the triumph of 
> fascism was the key factor in the demise (or rather defeat) of the 
> labor movement at the end of Weimar.  Moreover, none of the historians 
> of the Frankfurt school, I believe, have adequately analyzed the 
> impact and conditions of emigration on Institute work and positions. 
> Critical theory bears typical marks of radical emigrant thought in 
> that it is especially critical, impassioned, and contains novel 
> insights into both the culture and society from which it fled and into 
> the culture to which it has emigrated, along with corresponding 
> blindspots in both directions.  But it is also marked by increasing 
> isolation from a revolutionary movement or political struggles to 
> which it can relate. Thus, against Dubiel, I would argue that it was 
> the rise and triumph of fascism and the subsequent situation of exile 
> which  increasingly influenced the style, mode of presentation, focus, 
> and substance of critical theory which became more apocalyptic, 
> dramatic, ultra-radical, increasingly cut off from practical  
> politics, and individualistic.
>
>
>
> To be fair to Dubiel, it should be noted that his interest is not to 
> provide a detailed historical analysis of the facts and factors behind 
> the Institute's development of critical theory, but rather to provide 
> analysis of the conditions, structure, and organization of the 
> Institute's interdisciplinary program of social research.  This 
> project, mentioned in the Introduction, becomes the focus of the 
> second part of his book (119). Here Dubiel provides often fascinating 
> insights into how the Institute actually worked and interesting 
> analyses of the general structure and organization of 
> interdisciplinary social science.  This section should therefore be of 
> interest both to those interested in the history and modus operandi of 
> the Institute for Social Research and to those interested in how 
> interdisciplinary research might be organized.
>
>
>
> Dubiel admits that in his research into how the Institute actually 
> organized its investigations and publication projects several members 
> contested the key role which he and others ascribed to Max Horkheimer 
> (a point also contested by Herbert Marcuse in an interview with Jurgen 
> Habermas in @U(Telos) 38), and Dubiel admits that his interpretation 
> of Horkheimer's role is "somewhat forced."  However, I would suggest 
> that the concept of the "dictatorship of the Director," which 
> Horkheimer openly proclaimed and which Dubiel makes a defining 
> characteristic of Institute work, is more problematic than Dubiel 
> indicates.  Whereas Horkheimer may or may not have played the key 
> organizational and theoretical role in both the development and 
> presentation of critical theory, I would think that if the utopia of 
> the Institute for Social Research were reinvented that a more 
> democratic and less "dictatorial" structure might be preferable.
>
>
>
> In fact, as with most German and American followers of critical 
> theory, there are precious few critiques of Horkheimer or critical 
> theory in Dubiel's book.  During the last couple of pages, Dubiel 
> remarks that Horkheimer had a rather "naive concept of the empirical" 
> and did not adequately perceive how "theoretical initiatives in the 
> specialized sciences no longer came--and for some time had not 
> come--from philosophy but rather from the various disciplines 
> themselves; and that philosophy which stood in close relationship to 
> the specialized sciences, had disintegrated into a loose ensemble of 
> 'hyphenated' philosophies" (186).  But I would argue that the role of 
> philosophy within social theory during the materialism and critical 
> theory stages was neither obtrusive or excessive and that during these 
> periods the Institute achieved a rather nice balance between 
> theoretical construction and empirical research and that their 
> training in and use of philosophy played a generally constructive role.
>
>
>
> The problem with the trajectory of critical theory, as I see it, is 
> that with the breaking up of the interdisciplinary Institute during WW 
> II,  and with Adorno and Horkheimer's transformation of critical 
> theory from an interdisciplinary theory of society to a philosophy of 
> history, critical theory, at least temporarily, cut itself off from 
> both the sciences and political struggle and developments. 
> Consequently, the critical theory developed by Adorno and Horkheimer 
> in the 1940s and 50s became more hermetic, literary and philosophical. 
> But even this stage of critical theory contains many valuable texts 
> and insights, and I would suggest that what Dubiel described as the 
> first two stages of critical theory still provides models of an 
> interdisciplinary social theory with practical intent that continues 
> to be relevant today.  The different sort of radical philosophical 
> discourse developed by Adorno and Horkheimer during the 1940s--and 
> more or less practiced by them in most of their later work despite 
> attempts to resurrect the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt 
> during the 1950s--has its own special virtues and attractions but 
> seems to me quite different from the project of uniting philosophy and 
> the sciences which characterized critical theory in the 1930s (and 
> which also characterizes the last decade or so of Jurgen Habermas' 
> attempts to reestablish critical theory as a viable contemporary 
> social theory). Thus I believe that one of the contributions of 
> Dubiel's book is that he shows that critical theory contains various 
> projects, texts, and models which might be employed for varying 
> purposes in diverse historical circumstances.
>
>
>
> Moreover, I believe that Dubiel's book is of more than historical 
> interest in that it shows how interdisciplinary work might be 
> organized and shows how fruitful syntheses between philosophy, social 
> science, cultural critique, and radical politics might take place.  
> One of the enduring legacies of critical theory is therefore 
> illuminated by Dubiel's study: development of an interdisciplinary 
> radical social theory with practical intent. Whether this project 
> remains a nostalgic utopia of a bygone era or a viable model for 
> future work is one of the major questions posed by Dubiel's 
> interesting and challenging study.
>
>
>
> @
>
> Douglas Kellner
> Philosophy of Education Chair
> Social Sciences and Comparative Education
> University of California-Los Angeles
> Box 951521, 3022B Moore Hall
> Los Angeles, CA 90095-1521
>
> Fax  310 206 6293
> Phone 310 825 0977
> http://www.gseis.ucla.edu/faculty/kellner/kellner.html
> ----- Original Message ----- From: "Ralph Dumain" <rdumain at igc.org>
> To: <theory-frankfurt-school at srcf.ucam.org>
> Sent: Tuesday, February 28, 2006 9:56 AM
> Subject: [FRA:] Dubiel, Helmut. Theory and Politics (1)
>
>
>> Got this book yesterday--a fascinating approach to the program of the 
>> Institute for Social Research:
>>
>> Dubiel, Helmut. Theory and Politics: Studies in the Development of 
>> Critical Theory, translated by Benjamin Gregg, with an introduction 
>> by Martin Jay. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985.
>>
>> Contents
>>
>> introduction by Martin Jay      ix
>>
>> I. The Integration of the Proletariat and the Loneliness of the 
>> Intelligentsia: Political Experience and the Process of Theory 
>> Construction in the Frankfurt Circle, 1930-1945
>>
>> Methodological Procedure        3
>>
>> The First Phase: Materialism, 1930-1937 11
>>       Historical and Political Experience       11
>>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      23
>>       Theoretical Position      31
>>
>> The Second Phase: Critical Theory, 1937-1940    39
>>       Historical and Political Experience       39
>>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      49
>>       Theoretical Position      57
>>
>> The Third Phase: The Critique of Instrumental Reason, 1940-1945    69
>>       Historical and Political Experience           69
>>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      81
>>       Theoretical Position      88
>>
>> Summary 99
>>       Historical and Political Experience       99
>>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      100
>>       Theoretical Position      103
>>
>> Structural Change in Political and Historical Experience        109
>>
>> Notes to Part 1 113
>>
>>
>> II. Dialectical Presentation and Interdisciplinary Research: Theory 
>> Construction and Research Organization in the Institute for Social 
>> Research after 1930
>>
>> Introduction: On the Methodology of Interdisciplinary   119
>> Research
>>
>> The Program of the Institute for Social Research        129
>>
>> The Program in the Context of the History of Science    133
>>      The Philosophical Critique of Science and the Neopositivist
>>           Critique of Philosophy in the Weimar Republic           133
>>      The Relation of Theory to Empirical Research in Contemporary 
>> Sociology     136
>>
>> Theoretical and Historical Background   141
>>
>> The Theory of Dialectical Presentation and Research Organization 151
>>
>> The Cognitive Structure of the Organization of Research 155
>>       The Zeitschrift fur Sozialforschung       156
>>
>> Studies on Authority and the Family     164
>>       Analysis of the Circle's Cognitive Structure      168
>>
>> The Social Structure of the Organization of Research    173
>>       The Circle's Structure of Communication   173
>>       Role Differentiation within the Circle    177
>>       Conditions Determining the Institutional Framework        180
>>
>> Summary 183
>>
>> Notes to Part II        189
>>
>> Bibliography    191
>>
>> Index   205
>>
>> ------------------
>>
>> The methodological prelude includes a discussion of the conditions of 
>> a group's--in this case the Frankfurt School's--endeavors in the way 
>> of theoretical self-consciousness (reflection).  Dubiel explains his 
>> approach to the subject matter, e.g.:
>>
>> ---begin quote---
>> Our systematic representation of the early Frankfurt Circle is based 
>> on the following structure of points in inquiry:
>>
>> Historical and political experience
>>         The labor movement
>>         The Soviet Union
>>         Fascism
>>
>> Theory of the theory-praxis relation
>>         Subject and addressee
>>         Theory and praxis
>>
>> Theoretical Position
>>           Self-understanding within the tradition of historical and 
>> political theory
>>           Relation to Marxism
>>           Relation of philosophy to science
>>           Utopia
>> ---end quote---
>>
>> Dubiel's review of the Frankfurt School's self-understanding involves 
>> its assessment of contemporary conditions.    For example, in the 
>> first phase we see Horkheimer's critical assessment of the German 
>> Communist Party (KPD) in relation to its Stalinization and hence 
>> developments in the USSR, and an even more critical commentary on the 
>> Social Democrats (SPD).
>>
>>
>> _______________________________________________
>> theory-frankfurt-school mailing list
>> theory-frankfurt-school at srcf.ucam.org
>> http://www.srcf.ucam.org/mailman/listinfo/theory-frankfurt-school 
>
>
>
> _______________________________________________
> theory-frankfurt-school mailing list
> theory-frankfurt-school at srcf.ucam.org
> http://www.srcf.ucam.org/mailman/listinfo/theory-frankfurt-school
>
>



More information about the theory-frankfurt-school mailing list