[FRA:] Dubiel, Helmut. Theory and Politics (1)

Doug Kellner kellner at ucla.edu
Tue Feb 28 18:38:31 GMT 2006


Here's my review from mid-80s when the Dubiel book first came out=
b:dubiel.rev



Helmut Dubiel, Theory and Politics.  Studies in the Development of Critical 
Theory, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. and London, England, 1985), xiii and 
207 pages; translated by Benjamin Gregg.



Benjamin Gregg's translation of Helmut Dubiel's 1978 book 
Wissenschaftsorganisation und politische Erfahrung: Studien zur fruhen 
Kritischen Theorie) makes  accessible  to English-speaking readers one of 
the most important books yet to appear on the theory and politics of the 
so-called Frankfurt school. Dubiel provides the best available historical 
and analytical account of the development of critical theory, of its method 
of interdisciplinary social research, and of how it organized and pursued 
its research projects during its years under Horkheimer's directorship in 
Weimar Germany and in exile in the United States during the era of fascism. 
In the first half of his book, Dubiel focuses on "political experience and 
the process of theory construction in the Frankfurt circle, 1930-1945."  His 
study shows that, at least during this period, the Institute for Social 
Research was extremely interested in history, politics, and the relation of 
its work to its historical situation and revolutionary politics.  The texts, 
correspondence, and other material cited provides a strong defense against 
criticisms that critical theory is primarily apolitical, uninterested in 
history and politics, idealistic, and hostile to science. Dubiel's research 
makes it clear that the critical theorists took different positions during 
varying historical periods toward their socio-historical situation, 
politics, science, and theory.

    Dubiel divides the work of the Institute for Social Research during the 
period under scrutiny into three distinct stages: 1) materialism, 1930-1937; 
2) critical theory, 1937-1940; 3) the critique of instrumental reason, 
1940-1945.  He differentiates these stages according to the general 
theoretical position maintained,  the political position and presentation of 
the theory-practice relation, and their specific historical experience and 
positions toward the working class movement, fascism, and the Soviet Union 
during the period under question. Dubiel thus contributes both to a better 
understanding of the genesis of critical theory and to its developments 
under specific politico-historical  and theoretical exigencies. In 
characterizing the theory-praxis relation he distinguishes between the 
varying subjects and addressees of the theory and their differing 
conceptions of the relation between theory and practice in various 
historical contexts.  In particular, he shows how critical theory began by 
addressing itself to a revolutionary proletariat as part of the 
revolutionary movement and ended by addressing primarily other radical 
intellectuals in political isolation.

    In characterizing the dominant theoretical position during each stage, 
Dubiel analyzes the specific "self-understanding within the tradition of 
historical and political theory," the relation to Marxism, the relation of 
philosophy to science, and the concept of utopia operative. This sort of 
careful, differentiated historical and theoretical analysis makes possible 
appreciation of the heterogeneity of critical theory during its "heroic," or 
"classical," period and the significant developments within critical theory 
that have been generally overlooked by most historians or followers of 
critical theory, especially within the English-speaking world.  Theory and 
Politics thus provides an indispensible source for understanding both the 
history of critical theory and its fundamental theoretical position(s).



Dubiel argues that the, first, "materialism" phase of critical theory is 
distinguished by commitment to a materialist social theory defined by the 
unity of philosophy and science (11-38) and rooted in the marxian critique 
of political economy.  The distinctive contribution of this stage was 
development of a marxian social psychology and the major research project 
was a study of the social-psychological structure of employees in the Weimar 
Republic--which was recently published for the first time as @U(Arbeiter und 
Angestellte am Vorabend des Dritten Reiches) (Stuttgart: Deutsche-Verlags 
Anstalt, 1980) and was translated as The Working Class in Weimar Germany 
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1984)). Politically, there was 
"critical solidarity with the 'revolutionary wing of the working-class 
movement'" which characterized  the political orientation of the group (17).



     Eschewing both the mechanistic metaphysical materialism already 
criticized by Marx in The Holy Family, as well as the current positivistic 
forms of materialism, Horkheimer and his colleagues defined the objects of 
materialist theory in terms of existing social struggles, problems, and 
experiences. Rejecting Hegel's identity theory (and thus the forms of 
epistemological realism held to by many positivistic materialists then and 
now), for the critical theorists there was a non-identity between concept 
and object; their concepts and theories thus provided but pictures of the 
socio-material world and not any absolute or indubitable knowledge.  As 
Horkheimer wrote, "'Materialist theory...is not a metaphysics of history but 
a picture of the world that changes and develops in the context of practical 
efforts to improve it'" (33).



The materialist theory of society developed by Horkheimer and his colleagues 
was closely related to Marxism at this stage: "'Materialism is characterized 
by its content: the economic theory of society'" (34).  During this stage, 
the Institute saw its purpose as reformulating Marxian theory "under the 
historically changed conditions of capitalism and the labor movement" (34). 
This involved moving beyond crude marxian conceptions of the relation 
between base and superstructure and developing both a marxist social 
psychology and cultural theory to better analyze the mediations between the 
economic base and the realms of the superstructure.



The Institute's social theory during this phase was a response both to 
inadequacies within classical Marxism and the dominant forms of bourgeois 
science.  Orthodox Marxism had congealed into a dogmatic, reductionist, 
objectivistic metaphysical materialism, and bourgeois social science was 
characterized by a fragmentation of the sciences, each cut off from the 
other and pursuing its investigations isolated from other disciplines.  To 
overcome this dual crisis of Marxism and bourgeois science, the Institute 
attempted to develop an "interdisciplinary materialism" that would be 
characterized by an integration of philosophy and science. Accordingly, 
during the 1930s the Institute developed criticisms of both the abstract, 
speculative and metaphysical philosophy dominant in Germany at the time and 
the various specialized sciences. Thus, the project of constructing an 
interdisciplinary "materialist superscience" was conceived in opposition to 
both the specialized bourgeois sciences and the socialist scientism of many 
orthodox social democrats like Kautsky or communists like Stalin. As 
Horkheimer stated at the time:



"'Materialism requires the unification of philosophy and science. Of course, 
it recognizes technical differences between the more general research of 
philosophy and the more specialized research in the sciences, just as it 
recognizes differences in method between research and presentation but not 
between science and philosophy as such'" (36).



And in his inaugural address after taking over as Director of

the Institute, Horkheimer argued:



"'What matters today... is to organize investigations on the basis of 
current philosophical problems that unite philosophers, sociologists, 
economists, historians, and psychologists in an ongoing research community 
that can do together what in other disciplines one individual alone does in 
the laboratory, what genuine scientists have always done: pursue those 
questions aimed at the view of the whole, using the most refined scientific 
methods; reformulate the questions in the course of work as demanded by the 
object; make more precise and develop new methods without losing sight of 
general considerations'" (36).



During its "interdisciplinary materialism" stage, the Institute members saw 
themselves as part of the revolutionary labor movement, and supported 
efforts for a planned economy and the construction of socialism in the 
Soviet Union; they also saw fascism, in rather orthodox marxian terms, as 
the product of capitalism in crisis.  Dubiel's study is especially valuable 
for the way that it assembles materials defining both the Institute's 
theoretical and political positions at different stages of development, and 
how its members conceived the relation between theory and politics at 
different junctues.  Dubiel's assembled quotations are extremely well-chosen 
and illuminating and provide a useful compendium of Institute positions on 
both theory and politics.  In particular, he shows that, contrary to some 
misimpressions, the Institute took rather systematic and well-defined 
positions toward the political issues and movements of the day--at least 
until the 1940s.



During what Dubiel sees as the Insitute's second stage, they explicitly 
adopted the term  "critical theory" to characterize their work.  This stage 
(1937-1940) is marked by the defeat of the labor movement in Germany, the 
triumph of fascism, and increasing doubts about the Soviet Union as 
revelations of its trials, labor camps, and stalinist deformations became 
wide-spread.  This historical situation  required new reflections on the 
relation between politics and theory, the role of the radical intellectual, 
and the nature of socialism.  In essays published during this stage both 
Horkheimer and Marcuse "expressly emphasize that a change in property 
relations implies merely a negative precondition for the building of a 
socialist society" (42).  As Marcuse put it: "'Without freedom and happiness 
in the social relations of human beings, even the greatest increase in 
production, even the abolition of private property in the means of 
production, remains infected with the old injustices'" (42).



At this time, the Institute  adopted the term "critical theory" to define 
their theoretical position in part because conditions of exile in the United 
States forced them to adopt code words to describe their project to cover 
over their commitments to Marxism in an environment that was quite hostile 
to Marxism.   The label stuck and  many of its inner circle utilized it to 
define themselves to the present, and the Institute's theoretical labors as 
a whole are frequently subsumed under the blanket concept of "critical 
theory," though as Dubiel shows, this term was first coined in 1937 and 
henceforth was used to cover work in different contexts that was often quite 
different.



Theory and Politics documents the conditions and texts whereby the Institute 
developed a radical, neo-Marxian  social theory more appropriate to a 
situation when radical intellectuals are segregated, isolated, and 
marginalized.  Dubiel derives the title of the first section of  his study 
from  this situation: "the integration of the proletariat and the loneliness 
of the intelligentsia."  Critical theory represents a stage in the 
development of neo-marxist social theories during which radical 
intellectuals were separated from revolutionary socialist movements and 
fascism steadily gained power throughout the world. The Institute theorists 
were among the first to characterize this situation and to make explicit the 
problems for the marxian theory of revolution when the working class was 
defeated or integrated into capitalist societies.  This, of course, remains 
one of the defining features of the trajectory of critical theory to this 
day and points to why the Institute felt it was necessary to update and 
revise both the marxian theory and critique of capitalism, as well as the 
marxian theory of revolution and the transition from capitalism to 
socialism.



Thus, as Dubiel puts it, "By 1937, the subject and addressee of 
revolutionary theory are separated much more clearly in the Frankfurt 
Circle's political self-interpretation.  Horkheimer maintains repeatedly 
that, for the sake of the adequacy of the theory, the critical intellectual 
must be able to endure marginalization from the addressee of his theoretical 
work" (53). During this period, Horkheimer and his colleagues radicalized 
and developed their critiques of what they called "traditional theory" and 
further developed their theoretical position.  The political impasse 
evidently inspired more sustained theoretical labors.  The critical 
theorists still advocated a synthesis of philosophy and the sciences (63) 
but seemed more open to various empirical sciences and more critical of 
classical marxism. During the 1930s and early 40s, the critical theorists 
continued their work in developing interdisciplinary social theory and 
intensified efforts to develop a theory of fascism--projects that I shall 
shortly return to as they are the subject of the second half of Dubiel's 
book.



But probably the most significant development in the trajectory of the 
Institute's development was abandonment of the project of interdisciplinary 
social theory for production of the critique of instrumental reason which 
found classical expression in Adorno's and Horkheimer's @U(Dialectic of 
Enlightenment) (1947).  Although Dubiel describes the continued demise of 
the labor movement, spread of fascism, and oppressive developments in the 
Soviet Union at this time, he does not adequately explicate the conditions 
which led to the rather dramatic departures from their earlier theoretical 
enterprises.  While Dubiel notes the impact of WW II  (76) on the 
development of critical theory, he does not analyze in any detail the 
breaking up of the Institute's interdisciplinary group; this happened in 
part  because Horkheimer was forced to go to California on account of his 
health and because many of the Institute inner circle and other colleagues 
joined the U.S. government as part of their struggle against fascism.  At 
this time, Adorno and Horkheimer took over the development of critical 
theory and this stage is particularly marked by the imprint of Adorno's 
particular ideas and style of writing--a point not adequately explicated by 
Dubiel who tends to present Horkheimer as the demiurge of critical theory.



Adorno's and Horkheimer's work during this period is addressed to "critical 
intellectuals" and the pretense that they were writing for a temporarily 
defeated revolutionary movement is surrendered. Likewise, the attempt to 
integrate philosophy and the social sciences is replaced by more aggressive 
philosophical theorizing and speculation.  Given that both Adorno and 
Horkheimer were trained as philosophers, and in the absence of the 
interdisciplinary research Institute, it is not surprising that critical 
theory would turn more philosophical and radicalize its critique of science. 
This development was also conditioned by the instrumentalization of science 
and technology in the Nazi and other war machines and by Adorno's and 
Horkheimer's growing aversion to the sort of scientific philosophy and 
positivistic science dominant in the United States.  Consequently, the 
critique of instrumental reason and the "dialectic of enlightenment" 
replaced the earlier marxian emphasis on class struggle and materialist 
social analysis with a focus on the primacy of the relation between humans 
and nature, in which marxism, enlightenment rationality, science and 
technology, the culture industries, and the trends of development of both 
capitalist and socialist societies were interpreted under the rubric of the 
"dialectic of enlightenment." In this theory, projects like Marxism and 
science, intended to contribute to the domination of nature, turned into 
more powerful instruments for the domination of human beings.



On a theoretical and political level, Dubiel provides a fine analysis of the 
changed political and theoretical position developed by Adorno and 
Horkheimer during this period (67-97). Again, he chooses key passages to 
express their political isolation, their pessimistic conclusion that 
henceforth political radicalism could only survive in select critical 
intellectuals, and their more apocalyptic and elusive style of writing. 
Dubiel makes clear, against some of the devotees of critical theory, that 
important discontinuities emerged within the trajectory of critical theory 
and that the most significant discontinuities emerged in the 1940s in the 
break between this stage and the two earlier stages of development.



I would, however, take issue with some of Dubiel's conclusions stated in 
summary form after his historical, political, and theoretical analysis of 
the key stages of development within the Institute.  He claims that "The 
labor movement's demise at the end of the Weimar Republic was the most 
significant experience undergone by the Circle" (99).  This judgement is 
somewhat misleading, and I would argue instead that the experiences of 
fascism and emigration were the crucial determinants of key features of 
critical theory.  The inner circle of the Institute was never particularly 
interested in the vicissitudes of the labor movement and, in any case, the 
triumph of fascism was the key factor in the demise (or rather defeat) of 
the labor movement at the end of Weimar.  Moreover, none of the historians 
of the Frankfurt school, I believe, have adequately analyzed the impact and 
conditions of emigration on Institute work and positions. Critical theory 
bears typical marks of radical emigrant thought in that it is especially 
critical, impassioned, and contains novel insights into both the culture and 
society from which it fled and into the culture to which it has emigrated, 
along with corresponding blindspots in both directions.  But it is also 
marked by increasing isolation from a revolutionary movement or political 
struggles to which it can relate. Thus, against Dubiel, I would argue that 
it was the rise and triumph of fascism and the subsequent situation of exile 
which  increasingly influenced the style, mode of presentation, focus, and 
substance of critical theory which became more apocalyptic, dramatic, 
ultra-radical, increasingly cut off from practical  politics, and 
individualistic.



To be fair to Dubiel, it should be noted that his interest is not to provide 
a detailed historical analysis of the facts and factors behind the 
Institute's development of critical theory, but rather to provide analysis 
of the conditions, structure, and organization of the Institute's 
interdisciplinary program of social research.  This project, mentioned in 
the Introduction, becomes the focus of the second part of his book (119). 
Here Dubiel provides often fascinating insights into how the Institute 
actually worked and interesting analyses of the general structure and 
organization of interdisciplinary social science.  This section should 
therefore be of interest both to those interested in the history and modus 
operandi of the Institute for Social Research and to those interested in how 
interdisciplinary research might be organized.



Dubiel admits that in his research into how the Institute actually organized 
its investigations and publication projects several members contested the 
key role which he and others ascribed to Max Horkheimer (a point also 
contested by Herbert Marcuse in an interview with Jurgen Habermas in 
@U(Telos) 38), and Dubiel admits that his interpretation of Horkheimer's 
role is "somewhat forced."  However, I would suggest that the concept of the 
"dictatorship of the Director," which Horkheimer openly proclaimed and which 
Dubiel makes a defining characteristic of Institute work, is more 
problematic than Dubiel indicates.  Whereas Horkheimer may or may not have 
played the key organizational and theoretical role in both the development 
and presentation of critical theory, I would think that if the utopia of the 
Institute for Social Research were reinvented that a more democratic and 
less "dictatorial" structure might be preferable.



In fact, as with most German and American followers of critical theory, 
there are precious few critiques of Horkheimer or critical theory in 
Dubiel's book.  During the last couple of pages, Dubiel remarks that 
Horkheimer had a rather "naive concept of the empirical" and did not 
adequately perceive how "theoretical initiatives in the specialized sciences 
no longer came--and for some time had not come--from philosophy but rather 
from the various disciplines themselves; and that philosophy which stood in 
close relationship to the specialized sciences, had disintegrated into a 
loose ensemble of 'hyphenated' philosophies" (186).  But I would argue that 
the role of philosophy within social theory during the materialism and 
critical theory stages was neither obtrusive or excessive and that during 
these periods the Institute achieved a rather nice balance between 
theoretical construction and empirical research and that their training in 
and use of philosophy played a generally constructive role.



The problem with the trajectory of critical theory, as I see it, is that 
with the breaking up of the interdisciplinary Institute during WW II,  and 
with Adorno and Horkheimer's transformation of critical theory from an 
interdisciplinary theory of society to a philosophy of history, critical 
theory, at least temporarily, cut itself off from both the sciences and 
political struggle and developments. Consequently, the critical theory 
developed by Adorno and Horkheimer in the 1940s and 50s became more 
hermetic, literary and philosophical. But even this stage of critical theory 
contains many valuable texts and insights, and I would suggest that what 
Dubiel described as the first two stages of critical theory still provides 
models of an interdisciplinary social theory with practical intent that 
continues to be relevant today.  The different sort of radical philosophical 
discourse developed by Adorno and Horkheimer during the 1940s--and more or 
less practiced by them in most of their later work despite attempts to 
resurrect the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt during the 
1950s--has its own special virtues and attractions but seems to me quite 
different from the project of uniting philosophy and the sciences which 
characterized critical theory in the 1930s (and which also characterizes the 
last decade or so of Jurgen Habermas' attempts to reestablish critical 
theory as a viable contemporary social theory). Thus I believe that one of 
the contributions of Dubiel's book is that he shows that critical theory 
contains various projects, texts, and models which might be employed for 
varying purposes in diverse historical circumstances.



Moreover, I believe that Dubiel's book is of more than historical interest 
in that it shows how interdisciplinary work might be organized and shows how 
fruitful syntheses between philosophy, social science, cultural critique, 
and radical politics might take place.  One of the enduring legacies of 
critical theory is therefore illuminated by Dubiel's study: development of 
an interdisciplinary radical social theory with practical intent. Whether 
this project remains a nostalgic utopia of a bygone era or a viable model 
for future work is one of the major questions posed by Dubiel's interesting 
and challenging study.



@

Douglas Kellner
Philosophy of Education Chair
Social Sciences and Comparative Education
University of California-Los Angeles
Box 951521, 3022B Moore Hall
Los Angeles, CA 90095-1521

Fax  310 206 6293
Phone 310 825 0977
http://www.gseis.ucla.edu/faculty/kellner/kellner.html
----- Original Message ----- 
From: "Ralph Dumain" <rdumain at igc.org>
To: <theory-frankfurt-school at srcf.ucam.org>
Sent: Tuesday, February 28, 2006 9:56 AM
Subject: [FRA:] Dubiel, Helmut. Theory and Politics (1)


> Got this book yesterday--a fascinating approach to the program of the 
> Institute for Social Research:
>
> Dubiel, Helmut. Theory and Politics: Studies in the Development of 
> Critical Theory, translated by Benjamin Gregg, with an introduction by 
> Martin Jay. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985.
>
> Contents
>
> introduction by Martin Jay      ix
>
> I. The Integration of the Proletariat and the Loneliness of the 
> Intelligentsia: Political Experience and the Process of Theory 
> Construction in the Frankfurt Circle, 1930-1945
>
> Methodological Procedure        3
>
> The First Phase: Materialism, 1930-1937 11
>       Historical and Political Experience       11
>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      23
>       Theoretical Position      31
>
> The Second Phase: Critical Theory, 1937-1940    39
>       Historical and Political Experience       39
>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      49
>       Theoretical Position      57
>
> The Third Phase: The Critique of Instrumental Reason, 1940-1945    69
>       Historical and Political Experience           69
>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      81
>       Theoretical Position      88
>
> Summary 99
>       Historical and Political Experience       99
>       Theory of the Theory-Praxis Relation      100
>       Theoretical Position      103
>
> Structural Change in Political and Historical Experience        109
>
> Notes to Part 1 113
>
>
> II. Dialectical Presentation and Interdisciplinary Research: Theory 
> Construction and Research Organization in the Institute for Social 
> Research after 1930
>
> Introduction: On the Methodology of Interdisciplinary   119
> Research
>
> The Program of the Institute for Social Research        129
>
> The Program in the Context of the History of Science    133
>      The Philosophical Critique of Science and the Neopositivist
>           Critique of Philosophy in the Weimar Republic           133
>      The Relation of Theory to Empirical Research in Contemporary 
> Sociology     136
>
> Theoretical and Historical Background   141
>
> The Theory of Dialectical Presentation and Research Organization 
> 151
>
> The Cognitive Structure of the Organization of Research 155
>       The Zeitschrift fur Sozialforschung       156
>
> Studies on Authority and the Family     164
>       Analysis of the Circle's Cognitive Structure      168
>
> The Social Structure of the Organization of Research    173
>       The Circle's Structure of Communication   173
>       Role Differentiation within the Circle    177
>       Conditions Determining the Institutional Framework        180
>
> Summary 183
>
> Notes to Part II        189
>
> Bibliography    191
>
> Index   205
>
> ------------------
>
> The methodological prelude includes a discussion of the conditions of a 
> group's--in this case the Frankfurt School's--endeavors in the way of 
> theoretical self-consciousness (reflection).  Dubiel explains his approach 
> to the subject matter, e.g.:
>
> ---begin quote---
> Our systematic representation of the early Frankfurt Circle is based on 
> the following structure of points in inquiry:
>
> Historical and political experience
>         The labor movement
>         The Soviet Union
>         Fascism
>
> Theory of the theory-praxis relation
>         Subject and addressee
>         Theory and praxis
>
> Theoretical Position
>           Self-understanding within the tradition of historical and 
> political theory
>           Relation to Marxism
>           Relation of philosophy to science
>           Utopia
> ---end quote---
>
> Dubiel's review of the Frankfurt School's self-understanding involves its 
> assessment of contemporary conditions.    For example, in the first phase 
> we see Horkheimer's critical assessment of the German Communist Party 
> (KPD) in relation to its Stalinization and hence developments in the USSR, 
> and an even more critical commentary on the Social Democrats (SPD).
>
>
> _______________________________________________
> theory-frankfurt-school mailing list
> theory-frankfurt-school at srcf.ucam.org
> http://www.srcf.ucam.org/mailman/listinfo/theory-frankfurt-school 




More information about the theory-frankfurt-school mailing list