[FRA:] Horkheimer under review (2)
Ralph Dumain
rdumain at igc.org
Thu Feb 9 13:20:00 GMT 2006
Adorno vs. Horkheimer (1)
I have yet to grasp the difference. More quotes to come.
On Max Horkheimer: New Perspectives
ed. Seyla Benhabib, Wolfgang Bonss, John McCole
(1) Stefan Breuer, "The Long Friendship: On Theoretical Differences between
Adorno and Horkheimer," chapter 10, pp. 257-279.
Conclusion:
[begin quote]
Yet despite the indisputable influence that Horkheimer exercised on Adorno,
two things should be clear by now. First, Adorno's theoretical development
proceeded more continuously than Horkheimer's, as if to confirm Benjamin's
remark upon the publication of Kierkegaard book that the author's later
work would grow out of it. Both strands of argumentation we have pursued
in Adorno--the value form critique of "pure sociation" and of the "second
nature" produced by it, and the critique of the identity principle from the
perspective of the philosophy of history--are already adumbrated there,
before Horkheimer's version of critical theory took shape. It was only at
the beginning of the 1940s that Horkheimer managed a breakthrough to the
critique of idealism that Adorno had formulated in his early work. Even
then, he did so with serious reservations and never adopted the critique of
fetishism. The critique of bourgeois rationality represents a break in the
development of Horkheimer's thinking, whereas for Adorno it meant only an
extension of a position already established.
Second, if we weigh the elements these authors contributed to critical
theory against each other, it is Adorno's contribution that appears to
provide the more promising point of departure today. Although Horkheimer
provided critical theory with important impulses, his thought, down into
his late work, remained so close to idealism that fundamental insights into
the formal determination of thought and of sociation remained closed to
him. Because Horkheimer saw idealism not as the reflexive form of an
abstract society but as the preliminary appearance of truth, which he was
increasingly unable to mediate with reality, he was backed into a defensive
position that can scarcely be distinguished from that of late bourgeois
cultural criticism. The diagnostic capabilities of critical theory
increasingly yield to a posture that assigns to philosophy the task of
being "the remembrance and the conscience of humanity"--in other words, a
substitute religion (KT, 3:278). Consequently, in Horkheimer's late work
one hears more about original sin, the truth of theology, and the relevance
of Schopenhauer than about the architectonics of modern society.
Adorno on the other hand, kept critical theory open to experience and
diagnosis, perhaps because he had something in him of the attitude of the
collector and "natural historian" that he praised in Benjamin. However
inhibiting and theoretically sterile his unhistorical philosophy of history
may have been, it did not prevent him from opening himself to theories,
works of art, or phenomena of the culture industry in a way that is
unparalleled in critical theory. No work by Horkheimer or Marcuse displays
an intensity in confronting its object comparable to Adorno's studies of
Husserl or Heidegger in his Metacritique of Epistemology and Negative
Dialectics; none of the institute's contributions on mass culture can match
the penetrating analytical acuity of The Philosophy of Modern Music or the
studies on occultism, television, and film, whose significance for an
anthropology of the industrial age has barely been recognized. Whereas in
Horkheimer's work critical theory's diagnostic capacity vanished along with
its revolutionary hopes, Adorno shows that the future of critical theory
lies not in climbing back over "abandoned stages of reflection" but in an
opening to the present, even at the risk that its traditional categories
and concepts will thereby be confronted with hopeless paradoxes.
[276-7]
[end quote]
(2) Georg Lohmann, "The Failure of Self-Realization: An Interpretation of
Horkheimer's Eclipse of Reason," chapter 15, pp. 387-412.
[begin quote]
Horkheimer sees this concept [truth] preserved, in however distorted a
form, in the "great ideals of civilization--justice, equality, freedom";
"they are ... the only formulated testimonies we possess" (169/182).
Philosophy is to secure for itself the rational potential of these ideas;
though it denies their claim to "ultimate and eternal truth," it grants
"that the basic cultural ideas have truth values" (170/182). This view is
contradictory. If in critically examining the relation between ideal and
reality philosophy can "transcend them" (ibid.), then it may do so only
when, on the side of the ideals, its criterion of truth is justified. The
"basic difference between the ideal and the real" (171/183) characteristic
of this "true philosophy" is at the same time a relapse into metaphysics.
Adorno, consequentially, transferred the theoretical intention of truth to
the mimetic capacity. And in Negative Dialectics, he showed why, in his
view, truth defined as the correspondence between concept and reality
reinstates the domination of identity thinking. By contrast, Horkheimer
persists with aporetic "on the one hand, on the other hand" constructions.
He can only evoke a concept of reason able to wield a concept of truth that
would heal the "disease of reason." It would have to be a form of reason
that is not infected with the disease of "reason in civilization as we have
known it thus far" (164/176), hence a form of reason that is genetically
prior to all reason that, from the outset, has borne the subjugation of
nature as its mark of Cain." He believes of such a form of reason, oriented
to reconciliation with nature, that "by being the instrument of
reconciliation, it will be more than an instrument" (165/177)--a
paradoxical formulation, which once more only points out the failure of the
attempt to recover a comprehensive concept of reason.
In his careful reconstruction of the critique of instrumental reason,
Juergen Habermas has given a severe account of its aporetic outcome and
convincingly demonstrated why Horkheimer and Adorno had to run aground in
these aporias insofar as they wanted to reinstate a universal concept of
reason.
[407]
[end quote]
(3) Wolfgang BonB, "The Program of Interdisciplinary Research and the
Beginnings of Critical Theory," chapter 5, pp. 99-125.
[begin quote]
Despite his own postulates Horkheimer was in no position to think through
the concept of philosophy in a post-Hegelian form, nor could he imagine an
autonomous development of social research.
From this perspective, Adorno was more consistent. His "The Actuality of
Philosophy" (1931) at times suggests an alternative model for the program
of interdisciplinary materialism." Adorno interpreted the crisis of science
and philosophy as a transformation of the conditions of the possibility of
knowledge. He assumed that after the breakdown of the Enlightenment's
concept of reason, knowledge can only be produced negatively. To the extent
that the universalization of the commodity form eliminates the potential of
social life to oppose the existing structures, "only history now vouches
for the images of our lives." They appear only in traces, splinters, and
fragments, and deciphering them requires a concept of "preserving traces"
that goes beyond the "most refined scientific methods" in Horkheimer's
sense and points to a different form of scientific appropriation.
Of course, one may argue whether Adorno's version of the concept of
"preserving traces" can be reconciled at all with the program of an
interdisciplinary social science, but it can hardly be contested that his
argument took Horkheimer's critique of science more seriously and even
radicalized it. As Susan Buck-Morss has shown, on this point Adorno stood
much closer to the "dialectic of enlightenment" than to the concept of
"interdisciplinary materialism" and precisely this emphasis was probably
what hindered his line of thought from achieving more influence on the
development of early critical theory. For Horkheimer at the beginning of
the 1930s, there could be no question of anticipating the "dialectic of
enlightenment." Like Adorno, he saw an increasing trend toward
irrationalism but did not interpret these symptoms of a crisis as an
irreversible destruction of reason. Rather, they appeared as a temporary,
socially conditioned regression that was to be illuminated by the positive,
specialized sciences. And the integration of these sciences, in turn, was
understood to be fundamentally rational, inasmuch as the "detour" of
analyzing the regression would uncover the possibility of bringing about a
realization of reason.
[120]
[end quote]
More information about the theory-frankfurt-school
mailing list