Horkheimer on Logical Positivism
Ralph Dumain
rdumain at igc.org
Sat, 26 Apr 2003 11:41:27 -0400
Quote:
His first major broadside against Logical Positivism came in 1937 in the
Zeitschrift. [90] Once again his sensitivity to the changing functions of a
school of thought in different historical contexts was evident. Originally,
he argued, empiricism as practiced by Locke and Hume contained a dynamic,
even critical, element, in its insistence on the individual's perception as
the source of knowledge. The Enlightenment empiricists had used their
observations to undermine the prevailing social order. Contemporary Logical
Positivism, on the other hand, had lost this subversive quality, because of
its belief that knowledge, although initially derived from perception, was
really concerned with judgments about that perception contained in
so-called "protocol sentences." [91] By restricting reality to that which
could be expressed in such sentences, the unspeakable was excluded from the
philosopher's domain. But even more fundamentally, the general empiricist
stress on perception ignored the active element in all cognition.
Positivism of all kinds was ultimately the abdication of reflection. [92]
The result was the absolutizing of "facts" and the reification of the
existing order. [93]
In addition to his distaste for their fetishism of facts, Horkheimer
further objected to the Logical Positivists' reliance on formal logic
to the exclusion of a substantive alternative. To see logic as an analogue
of mathematics, he held, was to reduce it to a series of tautologies with
no real meaning in the historical world. To believe that all true knowledge
aspired to the condition of scientific, mathematical conceptualization was
a surrender to a metaphysics as bad as the one the positivists had set out
to refute. [94]
What was perhaps worst of all in Horkheimer's eyes was the positivists'
pretension to have disentangled facts from values. Here he detected a
falling away from the original Enlightenment use of empiricism as a
partisan weapon against the mystifications of superstition and tradition. A
society, he argued, [95] might itself be "possessed" and thus produce
"facts" that were themselves "insane." Because it had no way to evaluate
this possibility, modern empiricism capitulated before the authority of the
status quo, despite its intentions. The members of the Vienna Circle might
be progressive in their politics, but this was in no way related to their
philosophy. Their surrender to the mystique of the prevailing reality,
however, was not arbitrary; rather it was an expression of the contingency
of existence in a society that administered and manipulated men's lives. As
man must reestablish his ability to control his own destiny, so must reason
be restored to its proper place as the arbiter of ends, not merely means.
Vernunft must regain the field from which it had been driven by the triumph
of Verstand.
From: Jay, Martin. The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt
School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923-1950 (Boston: Little,
Brown and Company, 1973), pp. 62-63.
Naturally, I will have to check Horkheimer's own writings to evaluate this
paraphrase properly, and I have my doubts about Jay anyway, but I find this
characterization fascinating, both for its shrewdness and for the points at
which I find it jarring. Some observations:
(1) This would confirm the supposition that the real philosophical
players in the 1930s were indeed the positivists and the
irrationalists. Dialectical materialism is left out of account here, but
the Soviets had by that time botched it so badly that nobody else could do
anything with it, I presume. Other alternatives to positivism in the
scientific camp apparently did not register on the radar screen, for
example Roy Wood Sellars' critical realism, which was rooted in the
sciences and the tradition of American philosophy, but from an
anti-positivist perspective. (Whether Sellars had graduated to the point
of saying anything of importance about values at that point, I do not know,
and I doubt he was well-versed in the territory that the Frankfurters
covered.) In effect, Horkheimer was attempting in his own way to transcend
the positivism-lebensphilosophie divide, but he was stuck as everyone else
with the consequences of its legacy.
(2) The empiricist stress on perception was not just "passive", it was in
effect anti-materialist, an alienated abstraction. Sellars criticizes this
in his autobiography.
(3) Formal logic: it seems the Frankfurters were as confused about this as
the dialectical materialists. The fetishization of formal logic has to be
analyzed properly, not just from the point of view of its ideological
function in a social way, but in view of the fundamentally flawed
perspective of empiricism, which is anti-materialist and covertly
idealist. Both the Frankfurters and the dialectical materialists came out
of the Hegelian heritage, separate from the developments in formal and
mathematical logic, hence the latter two perspectives were never properly
assimilated by the same people, let alone integrated.
(4) Again, this characterization of Logical Positivism was shrewd, from the
perspective of its functioning in the total cultural system, which the
Frankfurters understood far better and the positivists were unequipped to
analyze at all, even those who were socialists. However, when we examine
closely the subtleties of these arguments now, we need to detect certain
lapses which indicate that the real integration of the formal and natural
sciences and the geistwissenschaften has not been accomplished. Maybe
someone has written something on this subject, but damned if I know who or
what.
Again, the link to excerpts from REFLECTIONS ON AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY FROM
WITHIN by Roy Wood Sellars; start at:
Foreword & Table of Contents:
http://www.autodidactproject.org/other/sellarsrefl-0.html
and follow the links.